Piecemeal Engineering a
Reduction in Juvenile Crime and Victimization
American University
Washington, DC
December 1, 1999
Plato claimed that through
change societies decay, and that democracy will decay into tyranny. Our experiences here in America are quite
the opposite. A democracy, through
change, can improve itself. If a
societal problem such as juvenile crime and victimization gets visibility, then
it can be dealt with. To best deal with
it our democracy might make several iterations of new laws and enforcement of
those laws. Each new enforcement
attempt or new law is then likely to be tested in the courts. In this paper we will look at how change
works in our democracy using the history of juvenile curfew legislation, enforcement,
and court tests. We will look at how
our system of governments adapts to a more and more reasonable limit of a
group’s freedom in exchange for a specific improvement in society. This can be seen as an example of Popper’s
piecemeal engineering.
Juveniles could
easily be dismissed as not of age and not ready for the liberty that adults
expect. They are under the control and
are the responsibility of other citizens, their parents. At first thought, it doesn’t seem
unreasonable to limit their freedom to protect them and others from their
immature actions. In fact that is what
parents are expected to do. On the
other hand it is a pretty serious matter in U.S. to deprive any group of any
liberty. Yet, since the 15 to 19 age
group commits 20.1% of all crime, it is worthwhile considering a reduction of
their liberties in exchange for a reduction in their crime (Korem, p28,
1994).
In 1993 Clinton took the issues
of family values and crime from the Republicans. In doing so, he encouraged the use of curfews to reduce juvenile
crime and victimization. This political
rhetoric exacerbated a trend of juvenile curfew legislation and
enforcement. A survey of 367 mayors
attending the 1995 National Mayors Conference showed that 90% of them consider
curfews to be a useful tool to curb juvenile crime and victimization (Donegan,
p108, 1993).
Alleyn Evans, an honor roll student, became a criminal one
ordinary Friday night, in December of 1998, and is now suing the city of San
Diego. Her parents had set a curfew of
11:30 p.m. for her that night, when they knew where and with whom she would
be. At 10:00 p.m., Alleyn was walking
one block from a coffee house to her friend’s car when she was approached by
police officers. They asked her age and
she told them she was 16 years old. The
officers then motioned for her to get into their squad car, in which they
brought her to the station. There she
was fingerprinted and photographed. She
repeatedly asked to call her parents and let them know where she was, but the
officers refused. Finally at 2:30 a.m.
the police called her parents, letting her father know they were holding her at
the station and for him to come get her.
Alleyn said, “I really felt like a criminal. Just because I was a
certain age, being outside was a crime,” (DiConsiglio, 1995).
San Diego,
California has a strict juvenile curfew that was brought into effect in June
1995 to crack down on teen crime.
Juveniles must be out of public areas from the hours of 10 p.m. and 6
a.m. There are penalties for parents of
repeat offenders, which can include fines that range from $100 to mandatory
attendance at a “parenting class”. The
law allows some exceptions for teens returning home from work or supervised
activities, but religious activities are not acceptable.
Alleyn Evans and her lawyers say the law violates their rights
guaranteed in the First Amendment of free speech and assembly, and the free
exercise of religion. The suit also
includes charges that the law is taking over the parent’s authority. Alleyn’s story makes one feel personally the
unfairness of a curfew. It is
understandable that she and her parents are fighting to reinstate some of her
basic freedoms.
The history of
juvenile curfews stretches back to 1880, when the first juvenile curfew
ordinance was enacted by the city of Omaha, Nebraska. (Hemmens and Bennett,
1999) Curfew laws became very popular in the 50’s in response to the tremendous
increase in the teen-age population. By
1957, more than half of the cities in the United States with populations
greater than 100,000 had curfew laws.
These were justified in order to protect juveniles from crime, reduce
juvenile crime, protect society and reinforce parental authority.
Typically,
these curfews in the early days required all juveniles to be off the streets in
the evening. Curfew laws varied greatly
from municipality to municipality. Some
had later hours for weekends and summers.
Some were enforced simply by picking up the child and taking him
home. Others required the offender to
be jailed temporarily. What is most
interesting about the laws and enforcement is how they have changed over the
years and what has caused the change.
Popper, in his
book The Open Society and Its Enemies, describes a means of social
engineering that fits this process of change quite well. He defines piecemeal engineering, as
practical problem solving without a clear end goal in mind. Here the problem to
be solved is reducing juvenile crime and victimization. Curfews are one of the possible tools. The difficulty with curfews as a solution is
the deprivation of liberty imposed on all juveniles in all circumstances. The interesting trend in curfew laws and
enforcement is how they are evolving to suit clearer and narrower goals and
with narrower limits on juvenile liberty.
The process is one of enacting a law or enforcement of a law, sometimes
with effectiveness statistics gathered, court challenges overturning the law or
changing its enforcement and then a new law starting the cycle over again.
While curfews
have been around for quite awhile, successful court challenges have only
occurred recently. Until the 1960s
juveniles were accepted as second-class citizens, subordinate to their parents. During the 1960s, the Supreme Court decided
on a series of cases that extended specific due process rights to juveniles.
(Hemmens and Bennett, 1999) Although, the court did hold that juveniles do not
have the same First Amendment rights as adults, Ginsburg v. New York,
(1968). In Bellotti v. Baird (1979),
the Supreme Court decided that juveniles generally have the same constitutional
rights, as do adults, but that the state may take into account in its laws the
special vulnerability of children and their inability to make decisions in a
mature and informed manner.
Juvenile
curfews have been challenged primarily as violating the First Amendment
freedoms of association and assembly, and the Fourteenth Amendment rights of
equal protection and due process. There
are historic standards of judicial review for challenges to these
amendments. In constitutional law, the
outcome of a case is determined by the standard of review and the facts of the
case. Depending on an implication of a
fundamental right or an affected suspect classification, the court uses strict
scrutiny or rational basis review.
“Fundamental rights are those freedoms that are essential to the
concepts of ordered liberty, they are rights without which neither liberty nor
justice would exist.” An example of
this is provisions of the Bill of Rights, like the guarantee of due process and
equal protection with the Fourteenth Amendment. Rights that are fundamental for adults, like the above mentioned,
may not be for juveniles due to their age. The Supreme Court states only race
and religion are suspect classification in all cases. Discrimination, based on suspect classification, is also
considered unconstitutional, though age is not a suspect classification. “Under strict scrutiny review, the state may
not enact legislation that abridges a fundamental right unless 1) it has a
compelling interest that justifies restricting a fundamental right and 2) the
legislation is narrowly tailored so that the fundamental right is not abridged
any more than absolutely necessary to effectuate the state’s compelling
interest.” Under rational basis review,
“the court will not strike down legislation that appears to have some rational
basis.” The government only needs to
choose means that are not totally unrelated to the success of the legislature’s
purpose. (Hemmens and Bennett, 1999)
Whether a right is fundamental
is key to the outcome of most cases.
With juvenile curfews one must decide if curfews impose on any
fundamental rights. If so, courts must then
apply strict scrutiny, which then would most likely find that curfews are
unacceptable. If they do not impose on
any fundamental rights, curfews will only be put through rational basis review
and almost certainly be found valid.
Many courts apply the rational basis to curfews because they believe the
state has a paternal responsibility for children, because children have lesser
rights than adults and because children can be treated differently than adults.
In 1898, the first juvenile
curfew case was decided. In Ex parte
McCarver, a Texas court decided the curfew ordinance to be
unconstitutional. The curfew ordinance
stated any person younger than the age of 21 was forbidden to be in public
streets after 9 p.m. except if a parent accompanied them or seeking medical
attention. The court declared the
curfew as “an invasion of the personal liberty of the citizen.” (Hemmens and Bennett, 1999) The age limit was a key factor.
In 1912 a new curfew was
brought to a Pennsylvania court. The
curfew stated that any person younger than the age of 16 was prohibited from
being on the streets after 9 p.m. The
exceptions being if a parent or guardian accompanied them or if they had a note
stating there was an emergency. This
curfew, in Baker v. Borough of Steelton, was found constitutional using
the rational basis review. It found
that the city had a justifiable concern in protecting the children from
possible harm. (Hemmens and Bennett,
1999)
The Iowa Supreme Court, in
1989’s Panora v. Simmons, upheld another juvenile curfew. In this
ordinance juveniles under the age of 18 are prohibited from being in a public
place between the hours of 10 p.m. and 5 a.m.
The court decided that no fundamental rights were implicated by the
ordinance. They then used a rational
basis review to come to their conclusion stating the state had legitimately
exercised it’s right in protecting society.
(Hemmens and Bennett, 1999)
However, three years later,
1992, the Iowa Supreme court declared, in City of Maquoketa v. Russell, a
curfew ordinance modeled on the Panora curfew unconstitutional. The city of Maquoketa had a similar curfew
to Panora stating that juveniles were prohibited from being outside after 10
p.m. Exceptions to this included: being accompanied by a parent, going
directly to or from work, or a “parentally approved supervised activity.” The opinion of the court was that the
juvenile curfew ordinance did in fact implicate fundamental rights of
juveniles, the First Amendment provisions of speech and association, and should
be reviewed under strict scrutiny.
Under strict scrutiny, it was determined that the ordinance was broader
than necessary to meet the city’s specific interest. (Hemmens and Bennett, 1999)
While applying strict scrutiny
review in the case of Qutb v. Strauss (1993), the Fifth Circuit of
Appeals found for the first time a Dallas curfew to be constitutional in
1994. The curfew prohibited juveniles
under the age of 17 from being in a public place from the hours of 11 p.m. and
6 a.m. on weeknights and 12 a.m. and 6 a.m. on weekends. The curfew also included many exceptions
such as being accompanied by a parent or guardian, running an errand for a
parent or guardian, running an emergency errand, traveling in a motor vehicle
to or from work, work-related activities, or interstate travel. Juveniles could still participate in
religious or civic organizations, attend school, or exercise First Amendment
speech and association rights. Minors
could also be on sidewalks in front of their home or a neighbors’ house. A key to Dallas’s success was the
presentation of data showing the amount of juvenile crime and the time of day
that a violent crime was likely to occur.
(McDonald, 1999)
San Diego began enforcing a
1947 ordinance for the first time in 1993.
Allowing for the exceptions of returning from work or a supervised
activity, the city's ordinance states that juveniles must be out of public
areas between the hours of 10 p.m. and 6 a.m.
In 1997, in Nunez v. City of San Diego, the Ninth Circuit Court found
San Diego’s juvenile curfew ordinance to be unconstitutional. It found the language to be too vague and
that it violated juveniles’ first amendment rights. However, it also indicated that a less restricted ordinance would
be acceptable. Within two weeks San
Diego passed a new ordinance very similar to the successful Dallas
ordinance. (McDonald, 1999)
In the year of 1989 the
District Court of Washington, D.C. declared the first attempt of a curfew
ordinance unconstitutional in Waters v. Barry. The District of Columbia’s ordinance attempt prohibited juveniles
from being in the streets or public areas between the hours of 11 p.m. and 6
a.m. Exceptions to the curfew
were: minors traveling with their
parents in a car, coming home from a job, or an emergency errand. The court found that the curfew did affect
fundamental rights and therefore applied strict scrutiny review. It decided that though the ordinance’s
purpose was to protect juveniles from harm, a state interest, it was not
narrowly enough written to achieve those goals. The court also stated that the constitutional rights of minors
are just as in need of protection as those of adults. (Hemmens and Bennett, 1999)
A new curfew was then
written. This curfew pertained to
juveniles and had exceptions copied from the Dallas curfew after it was upheld
in Qutb v. Strauss (1993). In 1996 this
curfew was taken to the district court with Hutchins v. District of
Columbia. Since there was not
sufficient evidence to treat juveniles’ fundamental rights differently than
adults, the ordinance was placed under strict scrutiny review. This time the District of Columbia did offer
enough information to validate its claim of state interest in reducing juvenile
crime and victimization. It also
pointed to the exceptions stating that it was fine-tuned. However, it did not convince the court, for
they again found the new curfew to be unconstitutional because the statistical
evidence was not supportive to their particular case. (Hemmens and Bennett, 1999)
Washington DC modified its
ordinance with an objective that was supported by adequate data and in the next
case of Hutchins v. District of Columbia the judges recently found the curfew
ordinance to be constitutional because it is related to achieving the important
governmental interest of protecting the welfare of minors. The ordinance
requires children aged 16 and younger to be home by 11 p.m. on weekdays and by
12 a.m. on weekends. Exceptions to this
include work, church activities, and if they cite their First Amendment
Rights. (The Economist, 1999)
As evidenced by the recent
District of Columbia ruling, legislation and court action have taken curfews a
long way from anybody under 21 off any street for any purpose after 9p.m. to 16
year olds and younger off specific streets after 11p.m. with many
exceptions. The trend across the
country has been to construct curfew ordinances that constantly narrow the loss
of liberty (location, time of day, age group, exceptions, etc.), while
maximizing the desired benefit for society, reduction of juvenile crime and
victimization. Our system of checks and
balances seems to constantly pit the forces for the desired societal benefit
against those forces that protect individual liberties. Our system seems to work quite well, despite
the predictions of Plato. Of course the
real key is whether or not curfews are effective. If they are not, then even this less restrictive ordinance is too
restrictive.
There are some remarkable
results from some of the cities using curfews.
A 1994 status report prepared for the city council of San Antonio, Texas
showed that during curfew hours juvenile victimization decreased by 42% in 1993
and 32% in 1994 (Kinnear, 1996, p198).
In New Orleans, 1995, a dawn to dusk curfew for youths under 17 drove
down crime 27% during restricted hours (Donegan, 1993, p108). The Dallas Police Department’s internal
analysis revealed that juvenile victimization during curfew hours decreased
17.7% in 1996. While these results seem
to be a powerful reinforcement of the value of curfews, there are
counter-claims that curfews do not have a significant effect. The claim is that juvenile crime and
victimization in the 90’s has gone down as crime rates in general have gone
down in the 90’s and that curfews displace crime to different locations and
times. Nonetheless, U.S. mayors are
enthusiastic supporters of curfews. A
1995 survey of the National Conference of Mayors showed that 75% of them had
curfew ordinances, up 45% since 1990 and 90% of the mayors believe curfews are
useful tools in reducing juvenile crime and victimization (Donegan, 1993,
p109).
Other means of reducing
juvenile crime and victimization are school and church outreach programs, more
police patrols in high crime areas, more aggressive enforcement of truancy
laws, mentor programs, harsher penalties for juvenile crimes, boot camps, adult
treatment for violent crimes, training in conflict resolution and others. There is not good data on these programs to
determine which one is better than the other.
The advantage to curfew ordinances is that the implementation is very
straightforward.
On balance, the statistics and
the enthusiasm of the U.S. mayors for curfews suggest that curfews are a useful
tool in reducing juvenile crime and victimization. Alleyn Evans would probably tell us that the trade off of the
deprivation of her liberty for the overall reduction in juvenile crime would be
too much for her. She might be right,
because in that circumstance she wasn’t likely to be either a possible juvenile
criminal or victim. The good news for
Alleyn is this process of piecemeal engineering a solution to the problem of
juvenile crime and victimization, is a continuous process of refining the
solution. The history of legislation
and court action, illustrated above, shows this to be true. Her suit may further refine and limit the
deprivation of liberty for juveniles.
DiConsiglio, J. (1998, November 3). The case of the girl who stayed out too late. Scholastic Update, 128, p6-7.
Donegan, C. (1993). Reducing Youth Violence: An Overview. In Bruno Leone (Ed.)
Youth Violence (p. 106). San Diego, CA: Greenhaven Press, Inc.
Fooks, S. (1998, Autumn). Young people and public space. Family Matters, (49), p57.
Fritsch, E., Caeti, T., and Taylor, R. (1999, January). Gang suppression through saturation patrol, aggressive curfew, and truancy enforcement: A quasi-experimental test of the Dallas anti-gang initiative. Crime and Delinquency, 45(1), p122-139.
Hemmens, C. and Bennett, K. (1999, January). Juvenile curfews and the courts:
Judicial response to a not-so-new crime control strategy. Crime and Delinquency, 45(1), p99-121.
Herring, J. (1999, September 13). Allow your teen-ager to earn trust. Knight-Ridder/Tribune News Service, pK5577.
Kinnear, K. (1996). Gangs: A Reference Handbook. Santa Barbara, CA: ABC-CLIO, Inc.
Korem, D. (1994). Suburban Gangs: The Affluent Rebels. Richardson, TX: International Focus Press.
Lights out. (1999, September 18). The Economist, 352(8137), p30-31.
McDonald, A. (1999, October). Major bummer for minors. ABA Journal, 85, p33.
Popper, K. (1971). The Open Society and Its Enemies: Part I – The Spell of Plato. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Rankin, J. (1999, March 5). Arlington youth committee nixes teen curfew plan. Business Press, 11(44), p4.
Sandel, M. (1996, September 2). Easy Virtue. The New Republic, 215, p23.
Town curfews: fair or unfair? Current Events, 98(12), p3.
Wood, D. (1998, June 10). As curfew critics grow louder, tide of support may be ebbing. Christian Science Monitor, 90(136), p3.
Copyright, 1999, Kimberly Joy Styslinger